exam questions

Exam LSAT Section 2 Reading Comprehension All Questions

View all questions & answers for the LSAT Section 2 Reading Comprehension exam

Exam LSAT Section 2 Reading Comprehension topic 1 question 145 discussion

Actual exam question from Test Prep's LSAT Section 2 Reading Comprehension
Question #: 145
Topic #: 1
[All LSAT Section 2 Reading Comprehension Questions]

Philosopher Denise Meyerson views the Critical Legal Studies (CLS) movement as seeking to debunk orthodox legal theory by exposing its contradictions.
However, Meyerson argues that CLS proponents tend to see contradictions where none exist, and that CLS overrates the threat that conflict poses to orthodox legal theory.
According to Meyerson, CLS proponents hold that the existence of conflicting values in the law implies the absence of any uniquely right solution to legal cases.
CLS argues that these conflicting values generate equally plausible but opposing answers to any given legal question, and, consequently, that the choice between the conflicting answers must necessarily be arbitrary or irrational. Meyerson denies that the existence of conflicting values makes a case irresolvable, and asserts that at least some such cases can be resolved by ranking the conflicting values. For example, a lawyer's obligation to preserve a client's confidences may entail harming other parties, thus violating moral principle. This conflict can be resolved if it can be shown that in certain cases the professional obligation overrides ordinary moral obligations.
In addition, says Meyerson, even when the two solutions are equally compelling, it does not follow that the choice between them must be irrational. On the contrary, a solution that is not rationally required need not be unreasonable. Meyerson concurs with another critic that instead of concentrating on the choice between two compelling alternatives, we should rather reflect on the difference between both of these answers on the one hand, and some utterly unreasonable answer on the othersuch as deciding a property dispute on the basis of which claimant is louder. The acknowledgment that conflicting values can exist, then, does not have the far-reaching implications imputed by CLS; even if some answer to a problem is not the only answer, opting for it can still be reasonable.
Last, Meyerson takes issue with the CLS charge that legal formalism, the belief that there is a quasi-deductive method capable of giving solutions to problems of legal choice, requires objectivism, the belief that the legal process has moral authority. Meyerson claims that showing the law to be unambiguous does not demonstrate its legitimacy: consider a game in which participants compete to steal the item of highest value from a shop; while a person may easily identify the winner in terms of the rules, it does not follow that the person endorses the rules of the game. A CLS scholar might object that legal cases are unlike games, in that one cannot merely apply the rules without appealing to, and therefore endorsing, external considerations of purpose, policy, and value. But Meyerson replies that such considerations may be viewed as part of, not separate from, the rules of the game.
It can be inferred from the passage that Meyerson would be most likely to agree with which one of the following statements about "external considerations" (line
53)?

  • A. How one determines the extent to which these considerations are relevant depends on one's degree of belief in the legal process.
  • B. The extent to which these considerations are part of the legal process depends on the extent to which the policies and values can be endorsed.
  • C. When these considerations have more moral authority than the law, the former should outweigh the latter.
  • D. If one uses these considerations in determining a legal solution, one is assuming that the policies and values are desirable.
  • E. Whether these considerations are separate from or integral to the legal process is a matter of debate
Show Suggested Answer Hide Answer
Suggested Answer: E 🗳️
The line reference takes us to the "external considerations" of line 53, which in turn takes us back to the "game" that was the subject of Q. 16. 3rd paragraph say that CLS scholars might try to break the analogy between the shoplifting game and legal rules by claiming that its impossible to form legal rules without making some moral judgments. That is, one has to bring in external considerations. But Meyerson counters that such considerations may be viewed as inherent in the rules of the game; in other words, those considerations may not be "external" after all. Applied back to the world of legal rules, we can therefore infer that
Meyerson would find it debatable whether the moral judgments are external to the legal world, as the CLS proponents suggest in their objection.

Comments

Chosen Answer:
This is a voting comment (?). It is better to Upvote an existing comment if you don't have anything to add.
Switch to a voting comment New
Currently there are no comments in this discussion, be the first to comment!
Community vote distribution
A (35%)
C (25%)
B (20%)
Other
Most Voted
A voting comment increases the vote count for the chosen answer by one.

Upvoting a comment with a selected answer will also increase the vote count towards that answer by one. So if you see a comment that you already agree with, you can upvote it instead of posting a new comment.

SaveCancel
Loading ...